Pagine

mercoledì 1 marzo 2017

[El Greco. The miracle of naturalness. The artistic thought of El Greco through the margin notes to Vitruvius and Vasari]. Part One


Translation by Francesco Mazzaferro
CLICK HERE FOR ITALIAN VERSION

El Greco.
Il miracolo della naturalezza.
Il pensiero artistico di El Greco attraverso le note a margine a Vitruvio e Vasari

[El Greco. The miracle of naturalness. The artistic thought of El Greco through the margin notes to Vitruvius and Vasari]

Edited by Fernando Marías and José Riello

Roma, Castelvecchi, 2017

Review by Giovanni Mazzaferro. Part One


E Greco, Portrait of an old man, 1595-1600, New York, Metropolitan Museum of Art
Source: Metmuseum.org via Wikimedia Commons

Other contributions on Giorgio Vasari in this blog

[N.B. On Vitruvius see in this blog also: Francesca Salatin, An Introduction to Fra Giocondo's Vitruvius (1511)Vitruvius, On Architecture, Edited by Pierre Gros. Translation and Commentary by Antonio Corso and Elisa Romano. Essays by Maria Losito, Turin, Einaudi, 1997; Giovanni Mazzaferro, Rare Books and a Great Discovery: a Specimen of Vitruvius' De Architectura Annotated by Cosimo Bartoli; El Greco. The miracle of naturalness. The artistic thought of El Greco through the margin notes to Vitruvius and Vasari. Edited by Fernando Marías and José Riello, Rome, Castelvecchi, 2017; The Annotations by Guillaume Philandrier on Vitruvius' De Architectura. Books I to IV. Edited by Frédérique Lemerle, Paris, Piccard, 2000; Marco Vitruvio Pollione's Architecture, translated and commented by the Marquis Berardo Galiani. Foreword by Alessandro Pierattini (unabriged reprint of Naples edition, 1790), Rome, Editrice Librerie Dedalo, 2005; Claude Perrault, Les Dix Livres d’Architecture de Vitruve, Corrigez et traduitz nouvellement en françois avec des notes et des figures, Paris, Jean Baptiste Coignard, 1673; Vitruvius, Ten Books on Architecture. The Corsini Incunabulum with the annotations and autograph drawings of Giovanni Battista da Sangallo. Edited by Ingrid D. Rowland, Edizioni dell’Elefante, 2003; Massimo Mussini, Francesco di Giorgio e Vitruvio. Le traduzioni del 'De architectura' nei codici Zichy, Spencer 129 e Magliabechiano II.I.141, Leo S. Olschki, 2003; Francesco di Giorgio Martini, La traduzione del De Architectura di Vitruvio. A cura di Marco Biffi, Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa, 2002; Francesco di Giorgio Martini, Il "Vitruvio Magliabechiano". A cura di Gustina Scaglia, Gonnelli editore, 1985.]

Finally, the Italian translation of the margin notes marked by El Greco to two samples of his library has been published: respectively, a sample of Vitruvius’s De Architectura in the version edited by Daniele Barbaro (1556) and one of the Giuntina edition of Vasari's Lives (1568). The annotations were first published in full in Spanish, respectively in 1981 [1] and in 1992 [2] and then were the subject of studies, which have spread to the other works owned by the Cretan painter. I would like to refer, as the most recent example, in particular to the catalogue of the exhibition The Library of El Greco, published in 2014 and already the subject of a review in this blog. I am recalling it because much of the information provided in that review (for example, the issue of the two inventories identifying part of the books owned by El Greco) will not be discussed here, to avoid repetitions for the reader, who is invited to refer to it.


El Greco, Christ healing the blind, about 1567, Dresden, Gemäldegalerie Alte Meister
Source: Web Gallery of Art via Wikimedia Commons

El Greco between naturalness and mysticism.

The title of the book, in itself, is already a program: "El Greco. The miracle of naturalness." What is naturalness? Can we talk about El Greco as a naturalist? All what remains written by the artist (who composed a treatise on architecture, which was not printed and is now lost) are about 18 thousand words resulting from the notes to Vitruvius and Vasari. These notes (this is the fundamental thesis of Mr Marías, then reinforced by Mr Riello) do not coincide with the artist's image which was formed in Spain around the turn of the century, according to which Doménikos would be a fundamentally Spanish artist, the precursor (or the founder) of a mythical national school, a deeply religious man, caught by mystical crises of which his paintings would be the most obvious expression. In his 18 thousand words in question, El Greco never addressed religious themes. Instead, he expressed his way of conceiving the 'naturalness'. And on this - I would say - there is nothing surprising: we are accustomed to speak of naturalism for the Carraccis, Caravaggio and so on, as if mannerism, classicism and anything else had openly proclaimed themselves 'anti-naturalists'. Obviously, it is not like this: even for Lomazzo or Zuccari (to give examples of Mannerist theorists related to the concept of an 'Idea' that is first formed in the mind), painting was an imitation of nature, and in fact it has remained so until the early years of the twentieth century. But here, I am leaving the floor to Mr Riello: "In fact, these margin records should become part of a large-scale debate, which would help to make all even more complex: the discussion concerning the current revision of the term "naturalism" and its consequences. In this sense, what is now being tried, with regard to the margin annotations, is: to deny their attribution, a difficult task since both internal and external hints attest that they were drafted by El Greco; to accept without any doubt that they were his own and then immediately to try to "kill the author" [...]; to question their contents, reading them in extremely pedantic way; [...] to bypass the author's intentions, a no less arduous task since the notes are, as I said, fully consistent with the practice of El Greco and, among other things, with the contents of his library; or finally to face the challenge that implies tying them to his prolific and varied artistic activity" (p. 63).

El Greco (attributed to), The Modena Tryptich, 1568, Modena, Galleria Estense
Source: Web Gallery of Art via Wikimedia Commons

Concretely, there are (roughly) three views: those who see El Greco as a schizophrenic artist, who wrote (for private use only, mind you, not to be read by others) incompatible things with his way of painting; others consider the artist as a "double converted" or as a painter who, during his surely unique biography, switched his style twice: first, from the "Greek manner" to the Venetian colouring; second, from the "Venetian (or, more generally, Italian) manner" to a religious and almost Expressionist mysticism (for them, the annotations belonged to a time when the second conversion had not yet occurred); still others (for what it is worth, this is also my view; more importantly, it is what Messrs Marías and Riello also think) see nothing but the development of a consistent thought (albeit expressed in a not particularly linear manner, as it is natural for any series of margin annotations) in which the artist did not deny anything, but rather developed and deepened his thinking.


El Greco, Portrait of Giulio Clovio (detail), 1571-1572, Naples, Capodimonte Museum
Source: Julije Klovic via Wikimedia Commons

El Greco and Vitruvius

El Greco’s notes to Vitruvius and to Vasari share their bitterness in the comment. There is no doubt that the polemical component played a fundamental role for him: such component, in the case of the comments to Vasari, suggests even the existence of some form of personal resentment. In this respect, there is a note which is not very clear ("This, and not I, is not what makes him furious”) that could somehow confirm a direct, and in this case probably not easy-going, acquaintance between the two. One may anyway believe Giulio Mancini, when he says in his remarks on painting that "when it turned necessary to cover some figures of the Last Judgment by Michelangelo, since they were estimated as indecent by Pius for that place, he [El Greco] came out with the statement that, if it had been decided to destroy the frescos completely, he would have made them again with no less honesty and decency than goodness of painting. Therefore, after he had made angry all painters and those who enjoy delight in this profession, he was forced to move to Spain" [3]. The episode, however, is perfectly consistent with what El Greco tells of Michelangelo. In fact, he judged him as a great sculptor and drawer, as a great architect, but as a bad painter, because of his technical inability to use oil painting and the totally inadequate range of colours (see the second part of the review).

It should be said that, from a theoretical point of view, the margin notes to Vitruvius are certainly more interesting than those to Vasari, because they seem to form a network of notes in preparation for the drafting of that treatise on architecture, which the son (an architect) gave account of after his father died; they constitute a more coherent theoretical structure than the annotations to Vasari, very biased because of the overwhelming weight of his personal hatred towards Vasari. One must ask, first of all, why El Greco worked for so many years at a treatise on architecture. It must be said that Pacheco, in his Arte de la Pintura, defined him as a 'painter philosopher' and reported that he dealt with all three arts: painting, sculpture, and architecture. Probably, more than because of the education of the child, it seems logical to think of a phenomenon of reaction against the triumph of Vitruvian classicism in architecture. In those years, 'Vitruvian' orthodox architects were triumphing in Spain for the construction of the Escorial. El Greco moved at first to Madrid, at the Royal court, but after a few years he withdrew to Toledo, most probably because he had not fully entered into the good graces of the Spanish court.

The cornerstones upon which the Cretan artist based himself are sufficiently clear: i) the primacy of painting over the other arts; ii) the construction of beauty based on the investigation of nature; iii) the speculative value of painting, as instrument of knowledge of the real and of the “invisible”; iv) form, light, colour and movement as the variables that contribute to the formation of beauty; v) the rejection of any mathematical proportion and every rule for the construction of beauty. Beauty must be proportionate in itself and the recognition of such proportion is the task of the 'judgment' of the painter, a 'judgment' based on experience and exercise (and therefore also on drawing); vi) rejection of the myth of antiquity as absolute perfection; antiquity can be emulated and must be improved. Under this viewpoint, the subject of El Greco’s shafts was not so much (or only) Vitruvius, who obviously could not be for him a counterpart with a historical perspective, but his interpreters, starting from Daniele Barbaro, who based himself on the Vitruvian teaching as a dogma and not as an experience, in order to bring together the theory of architecture. That said, it should however be noted that many margin notes, in any case, constituted a punctual commentary on technical aspects (for example, on the type of the temples and so on): El Greco entered thereby in a territory (that of proportion and of rules) that he simultaneously denied and that most likely he could not grasp in its entirety (as he was a painter and not an architect). 

El Greco, Retablo mayor of the church of the monastery of S. Dominic the Elder, 1577-1579, Toledo
Source: Web Gallery of Art via Wikimedia Commons
El Greco, Retablo mayor of the church of the monastery of S. Dominic the Elder, Assumption of the Virgin,
1577-1579, Art Institute of Chicago
Source: Google Cultural Institution via Wikimedia Commons

Painting

The second half of the Sixteenth century was the historical period of the triumph of architectural treatises. That age marked the years of the Vitruvian canon, of the 'rule' of the orders, of the mathematical proportion and, in some way, of the (sometimes implicitly given for granted) superiority of architecture on painting and sculpture. It was not so for El Greco. The architecture is "a simple human invention" and therefore this system of rules is a "necessarily particular" convention. It does not possess the ability to interpret nature. In this sense painting is instead superior, because it is with painting, which is basically camouflage, that the artist can make a 'judgment' on nature. Painting does not do it only through the reproduction of the form, but also (and especially) through colour and light effects: "painting is the only art that can judge of every object, shape, and colour, having as object the imitation of all; in short, painting has the function to address and model (or moderate?) all that you see, and if I was able to express in words what is the point of view of the painter, it would appear as a singular thing [... ]. But painting, being so universal, becomes speculative, because there is always the joy of speculation, since there is always something you can see, since even in a mediocre darkness you can see and enjoy and find something to imitate" (p. 24). Clearly, a naturalistic system pervades the art of El Greco. Whether this type of system is neo-Platonic or neo-Aristotelian is something that has been the subject of extensive debates. Normally El Greco has been classified among the Neo-Platonists, because Neo-Platonism fits better with the 'creation' of a mental idea that would correct nature. The artist was also considered as neo-Platonic because it is just sufficient to replace God for the Idea to explain his (alleged) mystical crisis and its (alleged) visionary painting, especially in his later years. Unquestionably, El Greco sided for the correction of nature. That said, it must indeed be noted that the word 'idea' never appeared in his eighteen thousand words, and El Greco never addressed religious issues. The 'speculative' essence of nature, the attention to optical phenomena, mediated by light and colour, all of this made of him a modern man of his time, and perhaps even a precursor (about twenty years later Accolti, Zaccolini and Cigoli wrote their treatises, all related to the question of the 'eye deception’) and there is no doubt that the "speculative activity" even in conditions of poor visibility approached him to the totally Aristotelian mentality of Zaccolini, who wrote his treatise on the basis of the experience of visual phenomena carried out in the Gulf of Naples.

Quite simply, El Greco was neither a neo-Platonic nor a pure neo-Aristotelian. He drew a number of suggestions from the two philosophies and tried to combine them into a personal solution. Without any doubt, from this point of view, his representation of the visible and invisible (i.e. the divine entities) was highly personal. In this respect, the view of the editors (perhaps explained in even more detail in The Library of El Greco, to which reference is made) is that the artist represents naturalistically the visible, while divine realities have instead their own, otherworldly beauty, in which the proportion is different from that perceived by the human eye. In his paintings, the two plans often intersect, but they do not indicate a creative fury that takes possession of the painter's hand and leads him into a sort of trance. Rather, again, they hint to a speculative approach even to the divine (which is also object of painting).


El Greco, Retablo mayor of the church of the monastery of S. Dominic the Elder, Holy Trinity,
1577-1579, Madrid, Prado Museum
Source: http://www.digibis.com/elgreco_digimus/es/musobjects/2725.html?ctx=freetext%3A0

Movement

Life is not a static fact, but it is made up of movement. I think it is particularly important to try to understand how El Greco tried to implement motion in his painting. Mr Marías speaks brilliantly on it: "The accentuated relief, the forced glimpses, the contortions of the figures - serpentine, flame-shaped, sinuous, in simple or crossed contrast - do not show us only their three-dimensionality, but also their movement, their different aspects, in an unstable, momentary, fleeting equilibrium. The elongation of the bodies gives them agility and beauty [editor's note: and it is not a mystical, but a speculative experience]; colour and the light give them a natural aura that circles the structures suggested by the artist's peculiar imagination" (p. 33). "In this sense, the smashing success, though limited from a social point of view, of the portraits of El Greco is not surprising. Likewise, we should not be surprised by the problems raised by his religious painting in Spain" (pp. 33-34). "El Greco, in his world, enjoyed success in portrait and admiration in religious painting, but was criticized for the lack of convenience and devotion of his sacred theme. He was supported by a narrow social and cultural group which evaluated more his art that his work in sacred genre, full of impropriety and formalistic distortions that belittled the content to which one was used."(p. 36).

El Greco, Spoliation of  Christ, 1577-1579, Toledo Cathedral
Source: Pictorpedia via Wikimedia Commons

Beauty

I talked a lot about beauty and its creation. At this point, it should not be totally surprising to note that, when speaking of architectural solutions, El Greco is much more attentive to beauty effects, or to what Vitruvio called venustas, rather than to the firmitas, the solidity of the building, which was - to the contrary - a bit the cornerstone of all sixteenth century architectural treatises and even the Vitruvian text (the reference is obviously to the triad firmitas, utilitas, venustas):

"Venustas embraces everything, because, being generated by proportion, it cannot miss from force except in the basement, where you have to beware any avarice" (p. 104).

What really matters is the gracefulness and variety of the building, whatever its destination, and that grace is a fruit of proportion. Once again - it is good to clarify - proportion must be "natural," and cannot result from a pre-established and untouchable set of geometric relationships. It is the result of the 'natural' human proportion (the architecture is anthropomorphic) which is wisely assessed by the architect's vision. In these circumstances, the firmitas is a consequence of venustas; it naturally follows, except for the building foundations, in which the relationship is reversed, and the first thing to do is to worry about the solidity of the basis on which the building will be built up. 

El Greco, The martyrdom of Saint Maurice, 1580-1582, Madrid, El Escorial
Source: Colleciones reales via Wikimedia Commons

El Greco and Scamozzi

In his commentary to the notations by Vincenzo Scamozzi to Giorgio Vasari's Lives (spread after 1600, that is at least ten years later than those of El Greco), Lucia Collavo suggests that it would be appropriate to compare the records of the Cretan artist and the architect from Vicenza, to recognize any common debt to their Venetian acquaintances. Today, thanks to this Italian translation, one can do it fairly easily. I find it more appropriate to do it here, actually comparing El Greco’s annotations to the De Architectura with those by Scamozzi to Vasari's Lives, because in fact this is the illuminating comparison. In both cases, in fact, the attitude vis-à-vis Vasari is common, and negative. But the reasons are opposite. By the way, it could not be otherwise, given that El Greco was a painter and Scamozzi an architect. Scamozzi criticised Vasari because it did not provide the 'measures' of the orders and spoke of perspective in a few lines only, while El Greco railed against Daniele Barbaro because he provided measurements and made a dogma of them. Scamozzi complained imprecision and failure to respect the classical canon also on the level of professional practice (consider the case of the Uffizi), El Greco refused to even consider just any corrective effect of the columns justified by optical phenomena; Scamozzi investigated antiquities, El Greco removed them. It is no coincidence that the instances of the Lives that are reported by Scamozzi as indicators of Vasari’s lack of professionalism (and which have to do essentially with architecture) are not commented by El Greco, because they did not interest him.


End of Part One
Go to Part Two 


NOTES

[1] F. Marías, A. Bustamante, Las ideas artisticas de El Greco. Comentarios a un texto inédito, Madrid 1981.

[2] X de Salas, F. Marías. El Greco y el arte de su tiempo. Las notas de El Greco a Vasari, Madrid 1992

[3] Giulio Mancini. Considerazioni sulla pittura pubblicate per la prima volta da Adriana Marucchi con il commento di Luigi Salerno, Vol. I, pp- 230-231. It should be added that the travelling of El Greco across Italy is by no way very clear. According to a (minority) thesis Domenico would not have moved to Spain in 1577 because he was 'hunted' by the Roman artistic circles, but he returned to Venice. From here, he would have run away in 1576 because of the plague.




Nessun commento:

Posta un commento