Pagine

venerdì 20 giugno 2014

Francesco Mazzaferro. Cennino Cennini vs. Leon Battista Alberti: variations on the concept of pictorial composition. Part three


CLICK HERE FOR ITALIAN VERSION

Francesco Mazzaferro
Cennino Cennini vs. Leon Battista Alberti.
variations on the concept of pictorial composition.
Part three


Fig. 32) Roberto Rossellini (1906-1977) – TV Series “The Age of Cosimo de’ Medici”. Part III – Leon Battista Alberti. Alberti admiring Donatello’s David. ©Flamingo Video 

NOTE: This is the last in a series of four posts dedicated to the comparison between Cennino Cennini and Leon Battista Alberti. Bibliographical quotations will be shown at the end of the last part. 

To begin from the first post, please, click here.


***


Latifah Troncelliti and the second analyses of composition in Cennini and Alberti, or how Cennino equalizes the result 1:1

Latifah Troncelliti, visiting professor in several US universities, is a philologist in romance languages. She has devoted an intriguing and well written monograph exactly to a comparison between Alberti and Cennini, heading to almost complete divergent conclusions from those of Rudolf Kuhn.

Her studies are in line with the above mentioned works of Julius von Schlosser. But the most direct source of inspiration is a 1971 essay of the Danish scholar Lise Bek. Lise Bek has made the first organic attempt to revisit the ‘classical’ terms of the comparison between the two authors, finding out important elements of symmetry between their works. I would certainly recommend everybody to read the essay. I would like to express my gratitude to the Academy of Denmark in Rome, for having provided me for that text.

Troncelliti’s starting point is that Alberti and Cennini were more or less contemporaneous. This most probably means that the existence of the young Alberti overlapped with the one of the old Cennini. However, while inhabiting Tuscany at the same time, they lived parallel existences, without meeting and knowing each other: the former, as a leading intellectual, fully backed by a comprehensive education and with a background as scholar in philosophy, rhetoric and science (but substantially ignorant of visual art in terms of practical implementation), integrated in and remaining confined to the upper class, without capacity to spreading his message to real artists; the second, as a practitioner who had been working in his youth in the highly successful workshop of Agnolo Gaddi, but had most probably failed to develop any successful activity as a painter with time and had turned therefore to write a manual on visual art techniques possibly as an alternative source of income, at the end of a long and difficult existence (which may have finished in poverty, like it happened to Paolo Uccello).

Cennini

For Latifah Troncelliti, Cennini is a painter of the very early Renaissance, but one who does not have any versatile cultural background backing his statements on art tecnique. He shares with almost the totality of other artists of his time (including mainstream authors of Quattrocento, with the exception of really very few ones of them) the feature of being first and foremost a craftsman, associated to a gild and excluded from both high education as well as from any possibility to have access to theoretical sources and learn from scholars. His strength resides in the very rich expertise he accumulated over years on visual art techniques, the direct knowledge of the activity of art workshops, and the clear understanding of the challenges with which their members were confronted daily.

Cennino also uses vernacular at a time when the young Italian language has not yet reached any precise definition of aesthetic concepts. For instance – according to Troncelliti – the definitions of ‘art’ and ‘science’, of their mutual relations and possible differences and overlaps are linguistically imprecise, and the terms are often used with a different meaning.

However, some aspects of Cennino’s writing are revolutionary, as they do not belong to any past art literature, nor will be included in any later works. The concept of phantasy (defined as the possibility to depict things which do not exist) is central to Cennino’s work, Troncelliti finds. She excludes it would be a derivation from Quintilian (as proposed by Leonello Venturi), and attributes it to an instinctive assessment by Cennino on the creative powers of artists. Alberti, to the contrary, states that “things which are not visible do not concert the painter”: there is no real space for imagination for him.

As also mentioned by Kuhn, the core role of phantasy does not imply, however, the attribution of a general licence to the artist to draw whatever he wants, simply following his own “creative demon”. There must be a system of limits to phantasy. While however Kuhn sees it in the ‘manner’ of the master (which each painter has to follow for years, before finding out his own style) Troncelliti refers to a complete different set of constraint to the painter’s phantasy, in Cennino’s views: the necessity to balance fantasy with observation of the nature. Naturalism and sense of dream co-existed in several painters of Quattrocento, first of all Botticelli, Troncelliti notes.

The absence of any rigid composition theory in the Book of the Art is an asset, and not a liability. Cennini offers a chance to the artist to experiment, when producing art. To the contrary, Alberti forces the artist to go through a rigid sequencing to achieve a composition, which limits the capacity to freely exercise ‘story telling’. Alberti also conceives composition as an abstract exercise, which has to be completed before implementation. On ‘narrative’, Cennino is less rational and more visual: for him the painter must be able to create on the spot a story, which must be in visible terms. Referring to Alberti, Troncelliti writes: “A story not yet represented is not a visual invention; it has no relation to Cennini’s fantasia, which moves and develops in the pictorial space and whose content refuses to be defined by conceptual thinking.”

It should be mentioned here that Latifah Troncelliti’s assessment on the treatise is in line with the positive criticism of a few scholars concerning the very few (and often of a very uncertain attribution) remaining art pieces of Cennino (on which a separate post will be devoted in this blog). This is in particular of the Hungarian scholar Miklós Boskovits, in his 1968 assessment of Cennino Cennini as a “non-conformist painter”: for him the critics’ prevailing negative assessment on Cennino as a non-original painter must be radically put into question. Contrary to what generally believed, Cennini was neither a Giottesque painter (Giotto was much too far away, chronologically) nor simply a disciple of Agnolo Gaddi, but the representative of a late-gothic style which combined forms of expressionism and naturalism. The role of phantasy in painting – says Boskovits – implies that Cennino intends to surprise, astonish and amuse his public, almost in a modern way. He is not at the search of an ideal concept of beauty; by intentionally refusing to stick to formal perspective techniques which were already well known, by focusing on the naturalistic descriptions of some details, by displaying and “instinctive, imaginary and often gross style”, Cennino wants to make an innovative use of phantasy. This thesis has been most recently confirmed by the publication illustrating the 2008 Berlin exhibition on “Cennino Cennini and the tradition of the Tuscan painting between Giotto and Lorenzo Monaco”, with the title “Fantasie und Handwerk”(Fantasy and Handwork), on which a separate post is being prepared.

Turning back to Troncelliti, while Cennino authors a treaty on painting, he is deeply convinced that his book alone cannot to make a good painter. He says it expressly: even studying day and night his book will not make a good painter. Therefore, what counts is being acquainted with practical methods helping a painter to express at best their talent. Moreover, he several times stresses the idea that a painter must be delighted of his daily work (a modern term used by Troncelliti would be ‘joy of painting’).

Cennini proposes a few operational composition techniques. First, Troncelliti explains the technology (based on the use of strings) through which Cennini would divide the painted area in regular geometric spaces. Quoting Judit Field, Troncelliti explains these methods are substantially similar to the one used by Masaccio in The Trinity.

Fig. 33) Masaccio, The Trinity, Santa Maria Novella, 1428 circa

Fig. 34) The Trinity geometric composition (See: http://www.kenney-mencher.com) 

More generally, Cennino recommends allocating figures in the ‘story’ through identifying central points, using them to allocate space among figures and develop central axes around which to develop stories. Only a few weeks ago, Amanda Lillie of the National Gallery has published an online article going into Troncelliti’s direction. Her view is that Cennini’s contribution to art theory has been significantly underestimated, and that his views on pictorial composition have been adopted by Renaissance masters, with a specific example on Raphael: the simple geometric structure underpinning the Garvagh Madonna.

Fig. 35) Raphael, 'The Garvagh Madonna', about 1509–10(Source: Amanda Lillie, National Gallery)
Fig. 36) Raphael, Underdrawing of 'The Garvagh Madonna'. (Source: Amanda Lillie, National Gallery)

Moreover, Troncelliti focuses on Cennini’s colour composition, based on colour contrasts. While Cennino pays a tribute to Aristotelian theories of a seven-colour scale, he also choses actual pigments to be found in nature (even recalling the search for colours he made together with his father), and describes their tonalities (seven kind of red, six of yellow, seven of green, three of blue). On gilding, he focuses on its use for textile only (differently from Byzantine painting), and uses it like Fra Angelico or Botticelli did. He uses colours to ensure relief in painting and volume. In his explanation of ‘sfumato’ he fundamentally describes techniques used in Quattrocento. He explains how to use natural sunlight in frescos, to avoid they would look like flat.

In conclusion, for Troncelliti Cennino Cennini is the prototype of a painter who decides to use his own direct expertise to write a manual for other painters: an artist writing for artists, a practitioner for practitioners. For him, composition has an eminently operational importance. Troncelliti says that Cennini should be included as in the same category as Ghiberti, Leonardo and Vasari. He belongs to a different category from Alberti who – as a non- artist – is the prototype of the art critic. Indeed – even more than Alberti – Cennino Cennini displays many techniques effectively used in early Renaissance, including composition techniques. It is the symbol of an art creator who tries taking in his own hands the transmission of his professional know-how, and does not accept the mediation of scholars and other cultivated experts. With the Counter-reformation, this category of artists will almost cease to exist, as artists will be deprived of the possibility to communicate directly – without the intermediation of art theory – with other artists.

Alberti

For Troncelliti, Alberti was – first of all – a master in rhetoric. He had the ability to re-package existing sources – mainly those from Greek and Latin origin – in a series of different areas and to draft new texts in a way to make them more easily readable and digestible to the educated public of his time. Original thinking, in this respect, was less necessary, and many arguments by Alberti, which have been analysed through the eyes of a very favourable literature following Jacob Burckhardt epic interpretation of the author, should be in fact more sombrely interpreted as merely rhetoric exercises.

While saying that he addresses painting as a painter in his treatise - says Troncelliti - Alberti did not really manage to turn to reason as a truly artist. Alberti’s claim that he his writing ‘as a painter for painters’ does not resist an analytical examination. He did not understand the fundamental importance of talent and motivation, and kept thinking that – as everything can be properly learned - his manual could help creating new generations of visual artists. He proclaimed the artists’ glory and reputation as the ultimate purpose of art, something which is often alien to true artists. True artists – writes Troncelliti – are more interested in their own art creations than in the social recognition they can gain among powerful members of the society.

Reversing an argument often used by others against Cennini, Troncelliti takes the view it was Alberti who in reality was not tuned with his own time’s visual art, while on the contrary art production in the workshops (and therefore the production of individual art works) occurred exactly according to Cennini’s prescriptions. There are at least four reasons why Alberti did not have any impact on the painting culture of his time (while he would have an important one later on, starting from Cinquecento).

First, as already mentioned, Alberti did not write for painters (and even the vernacular version he compiled of De Pictura would have been incomprehensible to a very large portion of that time of artists).

Second, Alberti’s real expertise on art practice was pretty limited. He mentioned his painting activity as a leisure activity only, and even his admirers – like Cecil Grayson – must admit that no work of him has remained, and that most probably their quality must have been pretty modest. More importantly – Troncelliti claims – all processes Alberti described in the treatise reveal (differently from Cennino) a profound incomprehension of the activity of a painter: in particular, of his necessarily ‘material’ activity as a craftsman, being confronted with the translation of creative impulses and conversion of materials into physical objects, and of the joy of material creation by passion.



Figg. 37-38) Roberto Rossellini (1906-1977) – TV Series “The Age of Cosimo de’ Medici”. Part III – Leon Battista Alberti: The Humanism – The Visual Pyramid. ©Flamingo Video 

Third, despite appearances, Alberti was extraneous to the prevailing naturalistic and realistic visual culture of his contemporaneous. Any realistic depiction of reality, writes Troncelliti, would have implied “to show ugliness as well as beauty”, like in a painting of Ghirlandaio displaying a diseased nose. Alberti lived in a neo-platonic world, in which only abstract beauty should be portrayed. His conception of beauty did not foresee the inclusion of the ugly side of the world, and was therefore not in line with Quattrocento.

Fig. 39) Ghirlandaio, An Old Man and his Grandson, ca. 1490, Louvre, Paris

Fourth, some of the most technical concepts contained in De Pictura have some mathematical faults, which made extremely difficult to implement them ad litteram. Repeating an already mentioned argument of Michael Baxandall, the scholar says that the only Renaissance artists who were able to correct and implement them are Mantegna (who found an empirical way out of the mistakes) and Piero della Francesco (who had a profound mathematical education).

Alberti theories may have been successful in later phases of painting, but not in Quattrocento. While Alberti dedicates the vernacular edition of De Pictura to Brunelleschi, and quotes in the introduction “our great friend Donatello” as well as Luca della Robbia, Lorenzo Ghiberti (called Nencio) and Masaccio, Troncelliti remarks that the examples of art works quoted by the author always date back to antiquity (they are therefore purely rhetorical references to Pliny, as all pieces of Greek painting went lost) and in a single case refer to Giotto. With the exception of Brunelleschi’s dome, none of the numerous masterpieces of the time is ever described, commented or used as example for the art theories propagated. There is also no historic proof of a close reciprocal relation between Alberti and Brunelleschi, as in Antonio Manetti’s Vita di Brunelleschi (Life of Brunelleschi) the two are shown as being in bad relations. Troncelliti even raise the hypothesis that Alberti may have not been aware of the individual works. In the case of Masaccio, moreover, he had already passed away at 28 years, before Alberti had returned to Florence from exile. Many of these arguments originate from Lise Bek’s above mentioned study.

The ultimate proof of Alberti’s alienation from his time is in his theory of colours, which has been defined by Samuel Edgerton “A Mediaeval Bottle without Renaissance Wine”. Alberti’s concept of ‘friendship of colours’, says Troncelliti, was basically focused on the use of black and white, and a reference to four basic colours (fir-colour, blue-grey, green of water, ash) he personally preferred, and would like to see to be used as much as possible.

In conclusion, Alberti assembled Greek and Latin sources to prepare a theoretical text on painting. However, his compilation did not reach out to artists, and the immediate impact of Alberti’s treatise on Quattrocento painting has been indeed greatly exaggerated. However, a new genre of literature was born: the one of a theory discussion on art principles, written by a non-artist for a public of non-artists. This was the birth of art criticism.


Thomas Puttfarken and the third analysis of composition in Cennini and Alberti: match suspended, there is no winner

The late Thomas Puttfarken authored in 2000 a monograph entitled “The Discovery of Pictorial Composition. Theory of Visual Order in Painting 1400-1800”. The first 180 pages of it are entitled: “Why the Renaissance did not Talk about Pictorial Composition”. What Puttfarken means is that – as far as today’s concept of composition is concerned, i.e. the one which had prevailed for centuries until the US critic Clement Greenberg proclaim the death of easel painting and formal composition – we are all children or grandchildren of France Baroque painting, from Poussin onwards. Explaining this further, Puttfarken takes the view that the concept of pictorial composition which Kandinsky and Mondrian still used for abstract art corresponds – in Quintilian’s rhetoric theory – not to compositio, but to the different and more elaborated concept of dispositio. The difference between the two concepts is that Italian Renaissance – applying to painting Quintilian’s compositio – could not figure out a pictorial composition in different terms but the way in which one or more bodies form a picture;  French Baroque, to the contrary, enlarged the concept (to use Rudolf Arnheim’s language) to a ‘total configuration of forces’ or – in the terms of Gestalt psychology – “a holistic Gestalt … with its self-contained nature, its regular shape and its more or less intricate and complex internal structure”. Pictorial composition is not only about the way in which paintings are structured. It is about “the way in which figures, objects and worlds conduct themselves in relation to the order of the image, and the degree of visual value and importance we attribute to them… The aim of pictorial composition, understood in this way, is not purely or primarily formal harmony; it is the visual conveying of meaning and significance”.  Rembrandt’s Syndics could be interpreted (in the traditional sense of compositio) as a horizontal and symmetric combination of six figures. More important (in the sense of disposition) is the compulsory feeling the Dutch painter creates in a viewer, like if the six figures were waiting for him and observe him entering in the room. Modern composition is in this sense creates ‘a sense of privilege’, which is at times a normal and uncomplicated one, at times very complex and even based on a subversion of visual order.

Fig. 40) Rembrandt, The Syndics, 1662, Rijksmuseum, Amsterdam

Puttfarken’s key reference seems to be Ernst Gombrich’s study on “Art and Illusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation” of 1960. In it Gombrich identifies a fundamental contrast in art between ‘order’ (represented by composition) and ‘life’ (represented by fidelity to nature). Italian Renaissance considered order as a traditional achievement and focused on fidelity of the representation of nature. “It has always puzzled historians – write Gombrich – that … there is no word about composition in Leonardo’s Trattato, and Vasari hardly uses the term”.

Cennini

Puttfarken also starts with Cennino Cennini, noticing that the terms ‘comporre’ or ‘componire’ (both ‘compose’) are used in three relevant passages of the Book of the Art. They indicate “a graver, a more important task” than simply drawing. “Since comporre is related, on the one hand, to the artist’s fantasia, his creative imagination, and on the other to the actual execution of the work, I may not be over-stretching my point in suggesting that the term is meant to denote the bringing into being – or giving reality to – the figure or istoria imagined by the artist.”

In the introduction, Cennino associate painting and poetry as the two disciplines which permit the poet to “compose and bind together, as he pleases, according to his inclinations. (…) In the same way, the painter is given the freedom to compose a figure, standing, seated, half-man, half-horse, as he pleases, according to his imagination”. Cennino – observes Puttfarken – refers to “composing a single figure”.

Cennino also refers to composition for painting of table painting and frescos. In the first case, he recommends: “The Charcoal wants to be tied to a little cane or stick, so that it comes some distance from the figure; for it is a great help to you in composing”. In the second case, he writes “Then compose storie or figure with charcoal, as I have described. And always keep your areas in scale and regular”.

Cennino mainly refers “to the spaces or areas that are to be occupied by the figures that the artist is about to compose”. Cennino also recommends, to this aim, to draw vertical lines “providing a central axis around which the figure can be drawn”, and horizontal ones displaying “the ground or horizon for the figure to stand on”.

This concept of composition does not corresponds to the one described by Puttfarken. “In Cennino, as later in Alberti, storia has to be understood as a narrative scene consisting of several figure, i.e. a scene telling a story. There is no reference as to how the figures should be arranged in relation to each other or to the picture as a whole”.

In this respect, says Puttfarken, Cennino may have not fully understood Giotto and Taddeo Gaddi and the previous two-three generation of painters to which he refers to as his source of inspiration. They had “invented or reformulated the order of sacred narrative”, “created new pictorial formulae”, “new types of images”. In other words, “they were not merely craftsmen”.

Puttfarken concludes that “being two generations removed from Taddeo Gaddi, and three from Giotto, probably means that Cennino – despite his own claims – does not directly reflect their ideas about their art, but a much watered-down workshop version shared by what is often called the Giotto school. Innovative or inventive composing was not necessarily part of the school system”.

Alberti

Despite all differences, also “Alberti’s notion of composition is neither derived from, or is it concerned with, the picture as an entity. It is derived from the observation of a single, individual object in nature and the way in which this object is visually made up of its surfaces. At its most basic level, composition is the activity of putting a thing together, and in this respect Alberti may well reflect the traditional usage of the term in the workshops as suggested by Cennino.”

Puttfarken also sees a parallel with Cennino, when Alberti analyses the definition of painting as made up of circumscription, composition and reception of light. “Circumscription, defined in its own right, is presented as a means of accurate imitation, based on precise observation. Composition, while employing drawing as its means goes beyond it in so far as it is a constructive or creative activity.(…)”

Nevertheless, Alberti has a more complex theory of composition. “When Alberti moves on from circumscription to composition, he explicitly advances from imitation to construction. (…) composition is the main area of artistic choice, the area where the artist has to decide and construct, rather than imitate. (…) Composition, perhaps even more than perspective, allows Alberti to justify the status of painting as a liberal art. Composition depends on the artist’s knowledge of the human body, its proportions, its movements and expressions of emotions, of the way in which the interaction of bodies can convey meaning, and it also depends on his ”

This does not exclude – however – that Alberti – as well as other Quattrocento art scholars - failed to talk about the overall effects of pictures. There are two reasons why Quattrocento art theorists could not do it. The first is the central role of the human body, the second perspective.

First, in Alberti’s theory the human body is “the paradigm of order and composition (…) a measure of perfection”. In functional terms, Alberti accepts that more bodies can create complex figures performing a joint action (which is called “historia, as a sum of all bodies, objects, etc.”) following “ordering principles [like] appropriateness of movements, both physical and mental, to the overall action aiming at a clear exposition of its meaning, and variety of movement, aiming at pleasure”. However, in more ontological terms – writes Puttfarken – “there is, for our Renaissance critics, no way of transcending the individual body. Two or more bodies do not from a greater whole. (…)”.

Second, perspective is considered by Alberti in the first book of the De Pictura: it is an a priori technical requirement of art, not a part of it. And still, Puttfarken finds that perspective (and in particular the traditional central perspective) “had compositional effects (…), recognised and practised by artists from an early date.” This “may have helped to render superfluous a separate theory of pictorial order and composition.” Indeed, Alberti himself – referring to the techniques to be used in order to construct perspective – writes: “This method of dividing up the pavement pertains especially to that part of painting which, when we come to it, we shall call composition.”

However, also in this case, it would be wrong to consider perspective – in Alberti’s definition – as a component of modern composition. Simplifying Puttfarken complex elaboration, there are two ways to construe the visual relation between the painting and the viewer. One is identifying the “central (…) visual ray that meets a surface at right angle”: this is the basis of Alberti’s theory of visual pyramid. The other one is the central ray which is not perpendicular to the surface, but to the eye of the viewer: this is real modern concept, where the viewer is at the centre of the composition. In other terms, Alberti theory’s is more related to the discussion of “an original single surfaces, a single overall visual pyramid, a single, immovable and permanently fixed centric ray and viewing distance”, in other terms “a single glance”. That single glance is imposed by the painter, and does not permit the viewer to interact actively.

Summing up, Puttfarken refers to Baxandall’s view on Leon Battista Alberti in “Giotto and the Orators”, as inventor of the composition: “my disagreement with Baxandall on this issue is a marginal one, yet perhaps not unimportant”.

It is interesting to see how different from Puttfarken’s arguments are the views developed by the scholars who edited the available versions in French of De Pictura. For Jean Louis Schefer, who published in 1992 the first French edition since the one of Claudius Popelin in 1868, the De Pictura offers to painters a theoretic frame which is dominated by the conversion of visual art into space through perspective. Schefer considers Alberti ’s crucial concept of historia as being conceptual part of perspective (and not - the other way round – perspective as an external scientific discipline, external to the concept of pictorial composition/narrative), and refers therefore to the projection of the spectator into the space of the painting (which is also the space of the invention). This active interaction is exactly what Puttfarken considers missing in Alberti’s composition. Thomas Golsenne and Bertrand Prevost, who edited a new version in 2004, do not only consider Alberti as the founder of the concept of ‘representation’, based on the concept of ‘historia’, but they contrast it with the previous concept of Middle Age (which they call, using a neologism they created, as ‘presentification’). They explain that Alberti’s representation has a different semiotic position than previous religious art. The classical Christian image in sacred art always pre-exists to the spectator (who is first of all a devote person), and has its power from religion. For Alberti, the pictorial representation is a pure representation, which absolutely necessitates a relation with a viewer.  Referring to Michael Foucault, they explain that Alberti’s historia has a double meaning: on the one hand it consists of the facts which are displayed in the painting and on the other hand it is the action of assigning a pictorial meaning to those facts. Thanks to the fundamental concept of ‘representation’, the De Pictura – conclude Golsenne and Prevost – transforms the position of the viewer in “an element absolutely necessary to the system of new painting. (…) The representation of painting does not exist as representation if not as an act of recognition by the spectators”. 


Bibliography

Alberti, Leon Battista – De la Peinture - De Pictura (1435), Traduction par Jean Louis Schefer, Paris, Macula, Dédale, 1992 – Owned by this library

Alberti, Leon Battista – De Pictura. Traduit du Latin et présenté par Danielle Sonnier, Pris, Édition Allia, 2010 - Owned by this library

Alberti, Leon Battista - De Pictura (Redazione volgare), edited by Lucia Bertolini, Firenze, Polistampa, 2011 (Edizione Nazionale delle Opere di Leon Battista Alberti. Trattatistica d’arte 1.1) – Owned by this library

Alberti, Leon Battista – La Peinture. Texte latin, traduction française, version italienne. Édition de Thomas Golsenne et Bertrand Prévost, revue par Yves Hersant. Paris, Seuil, 2006  – Owned by this library

Alberti, Leon Battista - On Painting, Introduction and translation by Cecil Grayson, Penguin Books, revised edition, New York, 2004 – Owned by this library

Aronberg Lavin, Marilyn, The Place of Narrative, Mural Decoration in Italian Churches, Chicago, 1990.

Aronberg Lavin, Mailyn - Un nuovo metodo per lo studio della pittura murale; il problema dell’ordine narrativo (A new method to study mural painting: the problem of narrative order), in: Storia dell’Arte 77, 1993, 115-122.

Baxandall, Michael - Giotto and the Orators: Humanist Observers of Painting in Italy and the Discovery of Pictorial Composition, 1350-1450, Oxford-Warburg studies, 1986 See: http://books.google.de/books?id=1sviuSWnAZEC&printsec=frontcover&dq=inauthor:%22Michael+Baxandall%22&hl=it&sa=X&ei=mQFQU8aDOMm8ygPfs4G4Dw&ved=0CC4Q6AEwAA#v=onepage&q&f=false

Bek, Lise – Voti frateschi, virtù di umanista e regole di pittore. Cennino Cennini sub specie Albertiana, in Analecta Romana Instituti Danici, 1971, pp. 64-106. Owned by this library (in the form of a pdf file kindly provided by the Accademia di Danimarca in Rome).

Blakeslee, David – A Journey  through the Eclipse Series: Roberto Rossellini’s The Age of Cosimo de’ Medici, 25 May 2011. See: http://criterioncast.com/news/a-journey-through-the-eclipse-series-roberto-rossellinis-the-age-of-the-medici/

Boskovits, Miklós - Cennino Cennini – pittore nonconformista, in : Mitteilungen des Kunsthistorischen Institutes in Florenz, Vol. 17, N. 2/3, pp. 201-222, Published by: Kunsthistorisches Institut in Florenz. See: www.jstor.org/stable/27652330

Burckhardt, Jacob - La civiltà del Rinascimento in Italia, Firenze, Sansoni, 1952 - Owned by this library
Burckhardt, Jacob - Die Kultur der Renaissance in Italien, Frankfurt am Main, Deutscher Klassiker Verlag, 1989 - Owned by this library

Burckhardt, Jacob – La Civiltà del Rinascimento in Italia - Un tentativo di interpretazione, edited by Maurizio Ghelardi, Torino, Nino Aragno, 2006.

Cennini, Cennino – Il libro dell’arte, edited by Fabio Frezzato, Vicenza, Neri Pozza Editore, 2009.

Di Stefano, Elisabetta – L’altro sapere. Bello, Arte, Immagine in Leon Battista Alberti, Palermo, Centro Internazionale Studi di Estetica, 2000 – See: http://www.unipa.it/~estetica/download/DiStefano_Alberti.pdf

Di Stefano, Elisabetta - Leon Battista Alberti e il doctus artifex (Leon Battista Alberti and the cultivated artist), in Mecenati, artisti e pubblico nel Rinascimento (Sponsors, artists and public in Renaissance), Pienza, 2009. See: https://www.academia.edu/990501/Leon_Battista_Alberti_e_il_doctus_artifex_  

Edgerton, Samuel Jr – Alberti‘s Colour Theory: A Mediaeval Bottle without Renaissance Wine, in: Journal of the Warburg and Courthald Institute, Vol. 32, 1969, pp. 109-134 See: http://www.jstor.org/discover/10.2307/750609?uid=3737528&uid=2134&uid=2&uid=70&uid=4&sid=21103995810787

Fantasie und Handwerk. Cennino Cennini und die Tradition der toskanischen Malerei von Giotto bis Lorenzo Monaco (Phantasy and Handwork. Cennino Cennini and the tradition of Tuscan painting between Giotto and Lorenzo Monaco), Gemäldegalarie Staatliche Museen zu Berlin, Hirmer Publishers, 2008 Owned by this library.

Field, Judith – The Invention of Infinity. Mathematics and Art in the Renaissance, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1977 See: 

Flemming, Willi – Die Begründung der modernen Ästetik und Kunstwissenschaft durch Leon Battista Alberti (The foundation of modern Aesthetics and Art Science by Leon Battista Alberti), Teubner, Leipzig and Berlin, 1916 (reprint from the collections of the University of California Libraries, 2014 – Owned by this library)

Garin, Eurgenio - Leon Battista Alberti, Pisa, Scuola Normale Superiore, 2013 - Owned by this library.

Gombrich, Ernst - Art and Illusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation, New York, Pantheon Books, 1960 See: http://www.scribd.com/doc/158411455/E-H-Gombrich-Art-and-Illusion-1984

Ilg, Albert - Das Buch von der Kunst oder Tractat der Malerei des CenninoCennini da Colle di Valdelsa, Quellenschriften für Kunstgeschichte und Kunsttechnik des Mittelalters und der Renaissance (Volume 1), Wien, Braumüller, 1871.

Kuhn, Rudolf - Alberti`s Lehre über die Komposition als die Kunst in der Malerei (Alberti’s doctrine on composition as the art in painting). In: Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte, Vol. 28, 1984, pp. 123-178. Available online at http://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de/4690/

Kuhn, Rudolf - Cennino Cennini. Sein Verständnis dessen, was die Kunst in der Malerei sei, und seine Lehre vom Entwurfs- und vom Werkprozeß (Cennino Cennini – His understanding of what is art in painting, and his doctrine on draft and implementation processes). In: Zeitschrift für Ästhetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, Vol. 36, 1991, pp. 104-153. Available online at http://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de/4689/

Kuhn, Rudolf – Erfindung und Komposition in der Monumentalen Zyklischen Historien Malerei des 14. Und 15. Jahrhundert in Italien (Invention and composition in the cyclical monumental history painting of 14th and 15th century in Italy), Peter Lang, Frankfurt am Main, 2000. Second, revised edition, dated 2005, available online at http://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de/4691/1/Kuhn_Rudolf_4691.pdf

Kuhn, Rudolf - Komposition und Rhythmus. Beiträge zur Neubegründung einer historischen Kompositionslehre  (Composition and rythm. Contributions to re-foundation of an historical doctrine of composition), Berlin, New York, de Gruyter, 1980. Revised version, available online at http://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de/4684/

Kuhn, Rudolf – On Composition as Method and Topic. Studies on the work of L.B.Alberti, Leonardo, Michelangelo, Raphael, Rubens, Picasso, Bernini and Ignaz Gunther. Tel Aviv Lectures, Peter Lang, Frankfurt am Main, 2000. Owned by this library.

Lillie, Amanda - Constructing the Picture, in 'Building the Picture: Architecture in Italian Renaissance Painting', The National Gallery, London, published online 2014. See: http://www.nationalgallery.org.uk/paintings/research/exhibition-catalogues/building-the-picture/constructing-the-picture/composing-the-image

Pictorial Composition from Mediaeval to Modern Art,  Edited by Paul Taylor and François Quiviger, The Warburg Institute, London – Nino Aragno Editore, Turin, 2001 – Owned by this library.

Pfisterer, Ulrich, Cennino Cennini und die Idee des Kustliebhabers (Cennino Cennini and the Idea of the art lover), in “Grammatik der Kunstgeschichte: Sprachproblem und Regelwerk im “Bild-Diskurs” (Grammar of Art History: Language Problems and Rulebook in the “Art Discussion”), Emsdetten, 2008, pp. 95-117 See:

Rossellini, Roberto - The Age of Cosimo de’ Medici (Part Three – Leon Battista Alberti, the Humanism), TV Series, Rai, January 1973 3 CDS owned by this library in the Italian version.

Schlosser, Julius ¬von¬: Materialien zur Quellenkunde der Kunstgeschichte - 1. – Mittelalter, Wien: Hoelder, 1914 See: http://digi.ub.uni-heidelberg.de/diglit/schlosser1914heft1

Schlosser, Julius ¬von¬: Materialien zur Quellenkunde der Kunstgeschichte - 2. – Frührenaissance, Wien: Hölder, 1915 See: http://digi.ub.uni-heidelberg.de/diglit/schlosser1915heft2

Schlosser, Julius von, Die Kunstliteratur: ein Handbuch zur Quellenkunde der neueren Kunstgeschichte, Wien, Kunstverlag Anton Schroll & Co, 1924 Owned by this library. See also: http://digi.ub.uni-heidelberg.de/diglit/schlosser1924

Schlosser, Julius von - Ein Kunstlerproblem der Renaissance: L. B. Alberti, Wien, Holder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1929 – Owned by this library.

Troncelliti, Latifah – The Two Parallel Realities of Alberti and Cennini. The Power of Writing and the Visual Arts in the Italian Quattrocento, Lewiston, Edwin Mellin Press, 2004 Owned by this library.

Venturi, Lionello – La critica d’arte alla fine del Trecento (Filippo Villani e Cennino Cennini), in: L’Arte, Rivista di Storia Medievale e Moderna, No. 4, 1925, pp. 233-244. See: http://digi.ub.uni-heidelberg.de/diglit/arte1925/0261?sid=4e7a93ea0aae0979cfd48cee654f4b71

Vuilleumier Florence,  Leon Battista Alberti - De la peinture, in: Revue de l'Art, 1993, Volume   99, pp. 84-85.

Wright Edward - Il De pictura di Leon Battista Alberti e i suoi lettori (1435-1600). Firenze, Leo S. Olschki, 2010 Owned by this library.

1 commento: