Pagine

lunedì 16 giugno 2014

Francesco Mazzaferro. Cennino Cennini vs. Leon Battista Alberti: variations on the concept of pictorial composition. Part Two


CLICK HERE FOR ITALIAN VERSION

Francesco Mazzaferro
Cennino Cennini vs. Leon Battista Alberti.
variations on the concept of pictorial composition.
Part two

Fig. 20) Roberto Rossellini, - TV series “The Age of Cosimo de’ Medici” – Part II – “The power of Cosimo” – Brunelleschi (centre) shows his plan for the Dom’s lantern 
to Cosimo de’ Medici (right) and Leon Battista Alberti (left) ©Flamingo Video 
[On Cennino Cennini, see in this blog:"Cennini Project".

On Leon Battista Alberti see in this blog also: Leon Battista Alberti, Descriptio Urbis Romae, Edited by Jean-Yves Boriaud e Francesco Furlan, Florence, Leo S. Olschki, 2005; and Rocco Sinisgalli, Leon Battista Alberti's new De Pictura, Edizioni Kappa, 2006. Please find below the first in a series of four posts dedicated to the comparison between Cennino Cennini and Leon Battista Alberti. Bibliographical quotations will be shown at the end of the last part.]

NOTE: This is the third in a series of four posts dedicated to the comparison between Cennino Cennini and Leon Battista Alberti. Bibliographical quotations will be shown at the end of the last part. 

To read the first post, please, click here.




Cennino Cennini, Leon Battista Alberti and pictorial composition

This note is about a very specific but relevant aspect: the way in which different art historians have analysed comparatively the concept of art in general and of art composition in painting, more specifically, in Cennino and Alberti. Three authors are considered. The first one is the German Rudolf Kuhn, emeritus Professor of History of Art at the University of Munich, who had several publications on the topic, including monographs and surveys on the concept of art and composition in Cennino Cennini, Leon Battista Alberti, the cyclical monumental art of Trecento in Italy and throughout Renaissance, published between 1980 and 2005. The second one is the Italian and US academic Latifah Troncelliti, romance languages philologist and art historian in several US universities (currently at Saint Bonaventure University, New York) who authored a monograph on “The Two Parallel Realities of Alberti and Cennini – The Power of Writing and the Visual Arts in the Italian Quattrocento” in 2004. The third one is another German professor of the history and theory of art, Thomas Puttfarken, who worked at the University of Essex in the United Kingdom, and authored “The Discovery of Pictorial Composition. Theories of Visual Order in Painting, 1400-1800”, published in 2000, shortly before his sudden death in 2006.

The three views are not presented in a chronological order, but in a sequence which aims at presenting the entire spectrum of ‘Cennini vs.Alberti’ comparisons, with the three authors assigning to Cennino three different roles: Kuhn’s view substantially confirms the thesis of Cennino’s weakness as a theorist, while Alberti is the inventor of the concept of composition; Troncelliti, to the contrary, sees in Cennino an artist already practising composition techniques of the Renaissance, while Alberti’s contribution to Quattrocento’s art is fundamentally questioned. While the first two authors do not hide their preference for either Alberti (Kuhn) or Cennini (Troncelliti), for Puttfarken they both belong to a phase of art which was not yet able to produce any elaborate concept of pictorial composition.

Figg. 21-22) Roberto Rossellini (1906-1977) – TV Series “The Age of Cosimo de’ Medici”. Part III – Leon Battista Alberti: The Humanism - The build-up of the facade of Santa Maria Novella in Florence (1973) 
©Flamingo Video 


Why composition?

The Latin term compositio figures out at the beginning of reflections on ‘how to compose’ in four different domains of art: rhetoric, architecture, painting and music.

In rhetoric, as seen in texts by Cicero and Quintilian, compositio defines the correct combination of words, and the construction of the sentence. As explained by Michael Baxandall, this concept did not refer at all to a comprehensive ‘literature composition’; it aims at securing that a hierarchy of rules ordered in four levels is respected: words create a phrase, phrases form a clause, and clauses form a period.

In architecture, compositio defines for Vitruvius the features of symmetry and proportion of a building, as a feature affecting visually the aesthetic of the building.

Fig. 23) Adriaen van Ostade (1610–1685), Self-portrait in the studio, 1663
Fig. 24) Giovanni Domenico Cerrini (1609–1681), The painter’s studio, first half of 17th century

In painting, compositio at the time of Cennino and Alberti was mainly the balance between bodies, their parts and other elements in the surface. Alberti offers a useful definition: “Composition is the procedure in painting whereby the parts are composed together in the picture. The great work of the painter is not a colossus, but a ‘historia’, for there is far more merit in a ‘historia’ than in a colossus. Parts of the ‘historia’ are the bodies, part of the bodies is the member, and part of the member is the surface (…). From the composition of surfaces arises that elegant harmony and grace in bodies, which they call beauty”. Baxandall notes the perfect symmetry with the above mentioned four-level concept of composition in rhetoric: surfaces form members; members are combined in bodies; bodies form the painting.

In music, compositio is used since the time of old Romans to design music production, and throughout all periods of Middle Age to define increasingly complex concept of music making. As from the Renaissance (with the cantus compositus, see the Treatise “Liber de natura et proprietate tonorum” – Book on the nature and the property of tones - by the Flemish Johannes Tinctoris, published in Treviso in 1476) composition defines the idea of polyphonic structures characterised by orderly vertical relations (intervals) between all participating voices.

What is common to these different uses of the same word? And why does this concept of “compositio” still matter today?

First, composition is a rule-based form of arts: it has to do with the orderly combination of certain key elements and with the production of an eventual art work through their combination, ensuring aesthetic results through measure, balance and ratio. By definition, this implies that composition identifies only one part of the artistic activity, excluding all those results which are exclusively or prevalently led by phantasy (fantasia, a term which Cennino included in his writing, opposing it to the ‘skill of the hand’ and therefore to the systems of recipes and rules which had described in the Book of the Art) or creation (ingenium, a term used by Alberti to define that part of painting which cannot be taught and learned, because it is immanently linked to the imaginative power of the artist). For instance, in music the opposition of composition is improvisation: the capacity to produce music without a defined music score (on which for instance jazz is based). 

Fig. 25) Johannes Vermeer (1632–1675), The Allegory of Painting

Fig. 26) Gustav Courbet (1819 –1877), The Painter’s Studio

Second, the term was at the origin much more limited in scope than today. For instance, ‘compositio’ as rhetorical organisation of a sentence is much smaller than today’s idea of ‘composition studies’, which have become an academic field of literature criticism. In music, the term ‘composer’ is used today for every musician producing his or her music; also sticking to more technical terminology in music, composition in English – as a subject of study, equivalent to “Kompositionslehre” in German, is much broader than the harmonic interplay between different voices. And without no doubt, the concept of pictorial composition has much evolved since the time of Cennini and Alberti (see for instance the recent colloquium of the Warburg Institute on ‘Pictorial Composition from Medieval to Modern Art’, opened by an essay on “Composition from Cennini and Alberti to Vasari” by Charles Hope and concluded by an essay entitled “Towards a Science of Art: the Concept of `Pure Composition' in Nineteenth– and Twentieth– century Art Theory” by Hubert Locher.

Third, notwithstanding these changes over centuries, the concept of composition still matter. There is a part of art where the aesthetic results do not depend only upon pure imagination and creative power, but where a system of rules, principles, identifying prescriptions also defines the overall value of an art work. Over centuries, artists have interpreted differently this core, trying at the same time to expand the scope of rules, and continuing to adapt them. The set of rules may therefore have become very different from the original system of rules (for instance in music, with dodecaphony) or a very elusive one (again in music, with aleatoric music), but still defines the difference with other art pieces where any system of rules has completely disappeared, and the art work is therefore conceived as a complete rule-less endeavour, which the public cannot interpret according to any previously agreed parameters.


Rudolf Kuhn and the first analysis of composition in Cennini and Alberti, or why Leon Battista beats Cennino 1:0

We owe to Rudolf Kuhn a monograph on the theory on pictorial composition (1980), two parallel essays on the concept of art and composition in Cennino (1991) and Leon Battista Alberti (1984), and one monograph comparing the concept of composition in Cennino and Alberti (2000). All of above mentioned writings are available in German only. The author has posted them in full in the net. Lessons at the Tel Aviv University in English are also available, from the year 2000.

Kuhn refers to the study of pictorial composition in terms of choice of persons, locations, events, appearance, disposition, decoration and figure schemes, modes, and overall narrative by the artist. In line with the work of Marylin Aronberg Lavin, he attempts to launch a new school of interpretation of history of visual art, based on the study of composition theory and techniques, rather than on the interpretation of historic context or on the art style. Turning to Cennino and Alberti, Kuhn’s main source of inspiration on the interaction between art theory and rhetoric is the last chapter of “Giotto and the Orators: Humanist Observers of Painting in Italy” by Michael Baxandall in 1971.

Cennini

Kuhn’s starting point on Cennini is a question mark. In Italian Trecento, fresco was the technique to produce monumental cycle of histories (Cimabue, Giotto, Taddeo and Agnolo Gaddi) and the same applied to the first part of Quattrocento (Benozzo Gozzoli, Ghirlandaio, Filippo Lippi, Piero della Francesca). “Narrative” and “story telling” or – in more technical terms - “pictorial composition” were therefore at the very centre of the painter’s know-how. Why is it so that Cennino Cennini – who lived among these two époques – did not devote an important part of his book to this core aspect?

The core aspect to consider, writes Kuhn, is that the Book of the Art is not a comprehensive treaty on all aspects of visual art creation. Cennino distinguishes between what is art creation by itself (it calls it fantasia, phantasy) and operazioni di mano (skills of hand). With one single exception (when Cennino says that painting – like poetry – gives the possibility to the artist to compose figures which do not exist, like centaurs), Cennino devotes his entire work to the second one only. According to Kuhn, the Book of the Art is expressly a handbook on the manual aspects of visual art production: nothing more and nothing else. It does not exclude composition and ‘story telling’ because it was an unknown concept, but because the author feels that a theory on it cannot exist, and only phantasy (independently of any possible theory) can lead the artist to compose stories.

Fig. 27) Bicci di Lorenzo, Annunciazione. 1414. Pieve di Santa Maria Assunta a Stia in Casentino (see http://mauriziobianchi.blogspot.com/)

Nevertheless – he says – some references to the concept of composition exist in Cennino’s book. Let us examine what they are.

Painting in Cennino’s world is mainly composed of two phases: design first and colouring second. Cennino describes in detail the method of designing and colouring on a wall or on a plate, both of which are based on a precise, rule-based sequencing of phases. Composing is one (non-autonomous) phase of sketching designs on the final image carrier. Kuhn explains that composition cannot be – in Cennino’s view – an autonomous activity of the artist, because it is part of a rule-based production cycle.

Composition – in this sense of being a rule-based phase of manual art production – is the distribution of the figures in space. It includes the identification of a single unit of measure for all figures, including architecture: that unit, says Cennino, is one third of the face of individuals (corresponding to the forehead of a person), ensuring both proportion of bodies as well as space proportion for figures and the story as a whole.

While composition is not an autonomous part of painting, this does not imply that the artist is not able of abstraction capacity. Cennino says that – through exercise – the artist will reach a level by which he will be able to conceive the designs “in his own mind”, before starting designing.

The lack of a theory of composition does also not mean per se that there are not composition rules which Cennini recommends, both for drawing as well as for colouring. On drawing (chapter 67), the Book of the Art contains the recommendation to follow measures and proportions among the figures, in particular making sure that spaces and distances among figures are maintained equal. Before colouring, he recommends to wait one day, to reconsider the composition. And on colours, Cennino suggests (chapter 29) that the equilibrium between dark, mixed and hell hues should be chosen in function of the ‘Storia’ and the figures to be represented.

In particular on the concepts of ‘spaces between figures’, Kuhn observes that it is not clear whether they are simply geometrical and abstract space relations, which are independent of the ‘history’, or whether they have to be in relation with the position and role of the main frontal figures. Only in the latter case, this might be considered a rule truly affecting pictorial composition.

The exclusion of ‘phantasy’ from the area covered by the Book of the Art does not imply by itself that the painter should be given full liberty of artistic creation, without any constriction set by an established method or theory. Cennini sees the build-up of a personal style as a long process, which inevitably goes through a long training (12 years, by rule) under a single master, of whom each disciple should adopt the ‘manner’. Only at the end of those 12 years the painter would be able to experiment his own style. 

In conclusion, Kuhn considers Cennini as not providing a theory of composition, notwithstanding that fact that ‘narrative’ and ‘story telling’ were the main features of painting cycles in those decades. Composition is also not seen as an autonomous part of visual art activity. However, Cennini recommends some composition techniques, both in terms of drawing as well as colouring. The lack of prescriptive composition theory does not imply that artists would be able to benefit of full creative liberty, as they are deemed to follow techniques and style of their masters.

Alberti

For Rudolf Kuhn, Alberti is the real inventor of the concept of composition in visual arts: the one who was able to translate the concept of compositio from rhetoric (as it had been conceived by Quintilian and Cicero) into painting, inaugurating a tradition which continued from him until Kandinsky, Picasso and later on.

While Alberti quotes in De Pictura the lost mosaic of the Navicella by Giotto as a valuable example of composition, for Kuhn two appropriate examples to see a combination of those typical figures are the Taxation for the Temple of Masaccio in the Brancacci Chapel of St. Maria del Carmine in Florence and the School of Athens by Raphael in the Vatican.

Fig. 28) Raphael, The School of Athens, 1509-1510


The starting point of Kuhn’s discussion on Alberti is the division of the De Pictura in three books. The first book includes mathematical and geometric basis of visual arts (including theory of perspective and colours), and therefore defines the contribution which other disciplines (geometry, optics) may give to art: this is what the artist needs to know, but it was not art by itself. His attention is therefore mainly on the second book, which describes “art” as a sub-set of painting. Art consists of those elements of painting which may be autonomously taught and learned. The third book (on the painter) includes all aspects of art more directly related to art creation, which – according to Alberti – cannot be systematised and framed in any theory, because they belong to genius, talent, creative power, and therefore to personal, inborn and not transmissible skills. As it was the case of Cennino (see above: contrast between ‘skill of hands’ and ‘phantasy’), Alberti defines a strict perimeter of the elements of art which can be properly transmitted to the reader through theory, covering them in the second book.

Alberti’s definition of art in the second book comprises three areas: circumscription, composition and reception of light. Circumscription and reception of light are – by and large – not radically different from Cennino’s basic concepts of ‘drawing’ and ‘colouring’. Composition is new, and sets up a system of rules which should contribute to achieve what Alberti defines (both in the Latin and vernacular version) as concinnitas: the painting must fit with a number of features which define its beautiful harmony. Several authors translate concinnitas as ‘elegant harmony’.  With a very modern word, it might be called ‘fitness’, i.e. a situation where all necessary elements fit nicely together.

Fig. 29) Raphael, School of Athens, compositional scheme, drawing by Gert Fischer ©Peter Lang - Courtesy

In a passage already mentioned in the first part of this blog, composition is construed in terms which are drawn from rhetorical texts to define the coordination between words, phrases, clauses and periods. The largest unit is what even Cecil Grayson (Alberti most important translator in modern languages) did not dare to translate from the Latin ‘historia’. Using modern language, I would perhaps say: narrative. The narrative is composed of ‘bodies’, any ‘body’ consists of ‘members’ (legs, arms, heads, etc.), and any ‘member’ is made of ‘surfaces’. The smallest unit of account of a composition is therefore a geometric concept (surface), on which Alberti had dwelled in the first book, describing surfaces as the basis of perspective theory: surfaces are created by the interception of objects with the visual pyramid.

Surfaces, members and bodies can all be composed. Kuhn explains that the composition of surfaces leads to the plasticity of figures, the composition of members to the movement of figures, and the composition of bodies to the action of figures. When all elements are composed, this leads to the universal plasticity of figures, the universal movement of figures and their universal action.

Interestingly, Kuhn also observes that Alberti does not set at the very centre of painting the portrait or the altarpiece, but the ‘story telling image’ (erzählende Bild), and that such images must aim at capturing the eyes of both the expert and the laymen.

Does the fact that story telling images (historiae) are ultimately composed of geometric surfaces imply that Alberti makes an unexpected early opening to abstract painting? Not at all, as compositions serve two purposes in visual arts: first, they express the richness of things in nature; second, they give an idea of the variety of positions and movements. Commenting on variety, Kuhn notes that this concept can not only be displayed through a multiplicity of physical differences but also through a richness of different mental and psychological attitudes.

While Cennini conceives composition as an integral phase of visual art implementation, for Alberti composition is an autonomous phase, preceding implementation, based on preparation of designs on paper.

Fig. 30) Raphael, study for a group and a figure for the School of Athens, Vienna, Albertina 
©Peter Lang - Courtesy

So far, following Kuhn, only those aspects of De Pictura have been mentioned which are included in the second book, since they belong to the concept of art, as a discipline which can be framed in a theory and may therefore be taught and learned. However, composition also includes aspects which cannot belong to the second book of De Pictura, as they do not simply reflect a system of rules, but are also the pure result of creative energy (ingenium). Also in Alberti’s case, the absence of rules does not imply that the painter can make whatever use of his creative powers. Here Alberti recommends avoiding an excessive fullness in the composition, maintaining appropriateness, dignity and equilibrium. He also recommends a combination of all colours, dark and hell ones.

Fig. 31) Raphael, study for a group and a figure for the School of Athens, Frankfurt, Städelsches Kunstinstitut 
©Peter Lang - Courtesy


In conclusion, Kuhn shows that Alberti has elaborated a complete theory of composition, as an autonomous part of visual art ideation, based on the combination of differently normalised, typical figures, and the interaction of bodies, members and surfaces. Composition helps story-telling and narration. 


Nessun commento:

Posta un commento